THE ROLE OF CONTEXT IN INTERPRETATION
1.1 Pragmatics and Discourse Context
Discourse analysis take account of the context in which a piece of
discourse occurs. Some of the most obvious linguistic elements which require
contextual information for their interpretation are the deictic forms such as here, now, I, you, this, and that. In order to interprete this
elements in piece of discourse, it this necessary to know (at least) who the
speaker and the hearer are, and the time and place of the production of the
discourse. The discourse analyst’s approach to linguistic data differs from
that of the formal linguist and leads to specialized use of certain terms. In
using terms such as reference, presupposition, implicature, and inference, the discourse analyst is describing what speakers
and hearers are doing, and not the relationship which exists between one
sentence or proposition and another.
1.2 Reference
In presenting the traditional view of reference, Lyons (1968: 404) says that ‘ the
relationship which hold between words and things is the relationship of reference : words refer to things’. Yet, Lyons, in a more recent
statement on the nature of reference, makes the following point: ‘it is the
speaker who refers (by using some appropriate expression) : he invest the
expression with reference by the act of referring’ (1977: 177). There is
support for such a pragmatic concept of reference in Strawson’s (1950) claim
that “referring” is not something an expression does; it is something that
someone can use an expression to do.
Example :
A: My cousin is
going to Bali + he’s happy
B: How long has
he been away for or has he just been
In the following conversational fragment, we shall say, for example, that
speaker A uses the expression my cousin
and he to refer to one individual. In the preceding conversational fragment, we
shall also say that speaker A treats the information that she has a cousin as
presupposed and speaker B, in her question, indicates that she has accepted
this presupposition. We shall take the view that the notion of presupposition
required in discourse in discourse analysis is pragmatic presupposition, that
is, ‘defined in terms of assumptions the
speaker makes about what the hearer is likely to accept without challenge’ (
Givon, 1979a:50).
1.3 Presupposition
Presupposition is what the speaker assumes to be the case prior to
making an utterance. The concept of presupposition is often treated
as the relationship between two propositions. In the case below, we have a
sentence that contains a proposition (p) and another proposition (q), which is
easily presupposed by any listener. However, the speaker can produce a sentence
by denying the proposition (p), obtaining as a result the same presupposition
(q).
Debora’s
cat is cute. (p)
Debora
has a cat. (q)
P >> q
When I say that Debora’ s cat is cute, this sentence
presupposes that Debora has a cat. In
Debora’
s cat is not cute.
(NOT p)
the same thing holds true, that is, it presupposes
that she has a cat. This property of presupposition is generally described as constancy
under negation. Basically, it means that the presupposition of a statement
will remain constant (i.e. still true) even when that statement is negated.
1.4 Implicature
In addition to identifying and classifying the phenomenon of
implicature, Grice developed a theory designed to explain and predict
conversational implicatures. He also sought to describe how such implicatures
are understood. Grice (1975: 26–30) postulated a general Cooperative
Principle and four maxims specifying how to be cooperative. It is
common knowledge, he asserted, that people generally follow these rules for
efficient communication.
Cooperative
Principle. Contribute what is required by the accepted purpose of the
conversation.
Maxim of
Quality. Make your contribution true; so do not convey what you believe
false or unjustified.
Maxim of
Quantity. Be as informative as required.
Maxim of
Relation. Be relevant.
Maxim of Manner.
Be perspicuous; so avoid obscurity and ambiguity, and strive for brevity and
order.
1.5 Inference
Inference is the act of drawing a
conclusion by deductive
reasoning from given facts. The conclusion drawn is also called an
inference. The laws of valid inference are studied in the field of logic. Human
inference (i.e. how humans draw conclusions) is traditionally studied within
the field of cognitive
psychology.
Accuracy of inductive inferences
The
process by which a conclusion is inferred from multiple observations is called inductive reasoning.
The conclusion may be correct or incorrect, or correct to within a certain
degree of accuracy, or correct in certain situations. Conclusions inferred from
multiple observations may be tested by additional observations.
Examples of deductive inference
Greek
philosophers defined a number of syllogisms,
correct three part inferences, that can be used as building blocks for more
complex reasoning. We begin with the most famous of them all:
- All men are mortal
- Socrates is a man
- Therefore, Socrates is mortal.
The
reader can check that the premises and conclusion are true, but Logic is
concerned with inference: does the truth of the conclusion follow from that of
the premises? The validity of an inference depends on the form of the inference.
That is, the word "valid" does not refer to the truth of the premises
or the conclusion, but rather to the form of the inference. An inference can be
valid even if the parts are false, and can be invalid even if the parts are
true. But a valid form with true premises will always have a true conclusion.
For example, consider the form of
the following symbological
track:
- All apples are blue.
- A banana is an apple.
- Therefore, a banana is blue.
For the conclusion to be
necessarily true, the premises need to be true.
Now we turn to an invalid form.
- All A are B.
- C is a B.
- Therefore, C is an A.
To show that this form is invalid,
we demonstrate how it can lead from true premises to a false conclusion.
- All apples are fruit. (True)
- Bananas are fruit. (True)
- Therefore, bananas are apples. (False)
A valid argument with false
premises may lead to a false conclusion:
- All fat people are Greek.
- John Lennon was fat.
- Therefore, John Lennon was Greek.
When a valid argument is used to
derive a false conclusion from false premises, the inference is valid because
it follows the form of a correct inference.
A valid argument can also be used
to derive a true conclusion from false premises:
- All fat people are musicians
- John Lennon was fat
- Therefore, John Lennon was a musician
In this case we have two false
premises that imply a true conclusion.
1.6 The Context Of Situation
2.1 Features of Context
Consider the two
invented scenarios in which an identical utterance is produced by distict
speaker.
- speaker: a young mother, hearer: her mother-in-law, place: park, by a duckpond, time: sunny afternoon in September 1962. they are watching the young mother’s two-year-old son chasing ducks and the mother-in-law has just remarked that her son, the child’s father, was rather backward at this age. The young mother say:
I don’t think Adam’s
quick
- speaker: a students, hearers: a set of students, place: sitting round a coffee table in the refectory, time: evening in March 1980. John, one of the group has just told a joke. Everyone laughs except Adam. Then Adam laughs. One of the students says:
I don’t think Adam’s
quick
(in each case phonological prominence is placed on Adam)
In both cases, the speaker
says of Adam that he is quick. The utterances in contexts of situation in which
they are cited, would be taken to convey very different messages. In (a) we
shall simplistically assume that the referents of I and Adam are fixed by
spatio-temporal co-ordinates. In (b) different referents for I and Adam are fixed spatio-temporally. This ‘Adam’ that he is being
compared (or contrasted) not with his father and favourably, but with the set
of the other students unfavourably.
2.2 Co-text
Co-text is the words which occur in discourse are
constrained by what,following Halliday. In the phrase like the aforementioned, the case that any sentence other than the first
in the fragment of discourse, will have the whole of its interpretation
forcibly constrained by the preciding text, not just those phrases which
obviously and specifically refer to the preciding text.
1.7 The Expanding Context
expanding
context is a principles which will determine the relevance or nature of the
specification.
1.8 The Principal of ‘Logical
Interpretation’ and of ‘Analogy’
Principal of local interpretation is principle that
instructs the hearer not to construct a context any larger than he needs to
arrive at an interpretation.
Tidak ada komentar:
Posting Komentar